IMR Press / JIN / Volume 18 / Issue 1 / DOI: 10.31083/j.jin.2019.01.105
Open Access Original Research
Theorizing how the brain encodes consciousness based on negentropic entanglement
Show Less
1 Faculty of Medicine, Universiti Sultan Zainal Abidin, 21300 Kuala Nerus, Terengganu, Malaysia
2 Centre for Biomedical Engineering, Universiti Teknologi Malaysia, 81310 Johor Bahru, Malaysia
3 Laser Centre, Universiti Teknologi Malaysia, 81310 Johor Bahru, Malaysia
4 Computational Optics Research Group, Advanced Institute of Materials Science, Ton Duc Thang University, District 7, Ho Chi Minh City, Vietnam
5 Faculty of Applied Sciences, Ton Duc Thang University, District 7, Ho Chi Minh City, Vietnam
6 Department of Oncology, Faculty of Medicine and Dentistry, University of Alberta, Edmonton, AB T6G 2R7, Canada
7 Department of Mechanical and Aerospace Engineering, Politecnico di Torino, 10129 Torino, Italy
*Correspondence: romanrichard@unisza.edu.my (R.R. Poznanski)
J. Integr. Neurosci. 2019, 18(1), 1–10; https://doi.org/10.31083/j.jin.2019.01.105
Submitted: 4 January 2019 | Accepted: 23 March 2019 | Published: 30 March 2019
Copyright: © 2019 Poznanski et al. Published by IMR press.
This is an open access article under the CC BY-NC 4.0 license ( https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0/)
Abstract

The physicality of subjectivity is explained through a theoretical conceptualization of guidance waves informing meaning in negentropically entangled non-electrolytic brain regions. Subjectivity manifests its influence at the microscopic scale of matter originating from de Broglie ‘hidden’ thermodynamics as action of guidance waves. The preconscious experienceability of subjectivity is associated with a nested hierarchy of microprocesses, which are actualized as a continuum of patterns of discrete atomic microfeels (or “qualia”). The mechanism is suggested to be through negentropic entanglement of hierarchical thermodynamic transfer of information as thermo-qubits originating from nonpolarized regions of actin-binding proteinaceous structures of nonsynaptic spines. The resultant continuous stream of intrinsic information entails a negentropic action (or experiential flow of thermo-quantum internal energy that results in a negentropic force) which is encoded through the non-zero real component of the mean approximation of the negentropic force as a ‘consciousness code.’ Consciousness consisting of two major subprocesses: (1) preconscious experienceability and (2) conscious experience. Both are encapsulated by nonreductive physicalism and panexperiential materialism. The subprocess (1) governing “subjectivity” carries many microprocesses leading to the actualization of discrete atomic microfeels by the ‘consciousness code’. These atomic microfeels constitute internal energy that results in the transfer intrinsic information in terms of thermo-qubits. These thermo-qubits are realized as thermal entropy and sensed by subprocess (2) governing “self-awareness” in conscious experience.

Keywords
de Broglie hidden thermodynamics
negentropic entanglement
guidance waves
negentropic force
macro-quantum wave equation
thermo-qubits
electron clouds
preconscious experienceability
consciousness code
1. Introduction

Molecular biologist, the late Francis H.C. Crick summarized one of our greatest intellectual challenges: to explain how consciousness1 (1 Consciousness means a process of preconscious experienceability (subjectivity) leading to conscious experience (self-awareness).) can arise from below brain chemistry (Crick:1994b):

“We all know that quantum mechanics is the basis of chemistry, so no one can say that quantum mechanics is not important. But what people are trying to say is that there is something more than chemistry involved. And I can’t see that they have any grounds for that yet. Because they have not shown even in outline, not even as a sketch, what mysteries of the brain’s function would be explained if something of this type did take place.”

Stuart Hameroff and Sir Roger Penrose (Hameroff:1996a, Hameroff:1996b) took the challenge and developed the “Orch OR” theory of consciousness. Although their avant-garde model cannot be criticized on the basis that consciousness needs to bridge the gap between micro- and macro-events in the brain, it can be criticized for not being a proper biological model (Georgiev:2007). The philosophical basis of the model is neutral monism whereupon conscious episodes arise not from matter, but from a sequence of quantum state reductions (wave-function collapses). Superposition is separation of space-time curvature which self-collapses causing consciousness to connect to the structure of the universe. Therefore, the “Orch OR” theory connects the preconscious intrinsically to the fine-scale structure of the universe by orchestrated quantum-state reduction in space-time geometry (see (Hameroff:2017) for a review). How experiential and physical entities arise from this aspectless neutral entity as advanced by the “Orch OR” theory remains highly contentious as a biological model of brain-based consciousness.

The electromagnetic force holds atoms and molecules together and thus is a determinant of atomic and molecular structure including protein turnover (Meijer:2018). In the pioneering days of quantum mechanics, pilot-waves guided by the electromagnetic field waves were developed in the 1920s mainly through so-called Bohr-Kramers-Slater model. However, the pilot-wave theory of de Broglie-Bohm (see De:1987 and (Bohm:1990) for a review) is independent of the electromagnetic field. The pilot-wave theory represents a more fundamental theory whereupon an electron is a particle at its core and an active field surrounds the core where the latter guides the motion of the electron referred to as a guiding wave. This active field represents internal energy is due to ‘hidden’ thermodynamics according to de Broglie’s wave theory. (Bohm:1952) called this energy his ‘quantum potential’. The de Broglie-Bohm theory is applicable at the sub-atomic scale (10 - 15 m) but may produce changes of negligible importance at the atomic scale of 0.1 nm (10 - 10 m) or above, including the macro-quantum realm. This realm borders quantum physics and quantum chemistry. It can be quantified to be the scale where quantum processes prevail over classical processes.

The subtle changes inherent at the macro-quantum realm can be deciphered in terms of phase differences in thermo-quantum oscillations of electron clouds. Their existence depends on whether thermo-quantum fluctuations dominate over thermal fluctuations (Brownian motion). According to (Beck:1992) fewer than ten electrons suffice to ensure quantum processes prevail over thermal processes at typical length scales of the order of several nanometers. The classification of fluctuations as thermo-quantum or thermal depends on the thermal de Broglie wavelength expressed as follows:

λ = 2 π 2 m κ B T
where = h 2 π is the reduced Planck constant ( h = 6.6 × 10 - 34 Js is the Planck constant), m = 9.10 × 10 - 31 kg is the mass of electron multiplied by the number of electrons, κ B = 1.38 × 10 - 23 JK - 1 is the Boltzmann constant and T = 310 K is the body temperature. For example, if m = 10 electron masses and T = 310 K it follows that the thermal de Broglie wavelength is a few nanometers. Hence if the average molecular dipole-bound electron distance ( L ) at scales of few nanometers λ L then the fluctuations can be treated classically. However, for greater number of electrons with an average molecular dipole-bound electron distance, for example at the femtometer scale λ L , thermo-quantum fluctuations dominate.

The de Broglie-Bohm theory being observer independent portrays consciousness to be not fundamental but arising from the intrinsic constituency of matter. In a non-reductionist perspective, consciousness co-exists with cognition and has an affect according to “biological naturalism” (Searle:2007). What this means is that consciousness has no causal attribute to effect cognition due to its lability, but consciousness affects the brain for cognition to decode consciousness in memory as conscious experience (self-awareness). The affective role stems from the composite of magnetic dipole moments forming an electromagnetic field as opposed to an effective role in the presence of a pre-existing electromagnetic field associated with cognition. Note that, free electrons are evanescent in the cerebral fluid. Excited water molecules are destroyed with the formation of ions, and electrons capture water molecules and become solvated: H 2 O H + + OH - . The mass of the ion OH - is about 16 masses of the hydronium ion H + is 2.7 ×10 × 10 - 26 kg. From Eq. 1 it follows that λ 1Å. That is, this ion can migrate on a length comparable to the intermolecular spacing, about 7 Å. Having lost most of the energy for excitation and ionization of water molecules, the electron continues to interact with the surrounding water molecules until it is in the potential barrier, since it cannot overcome the electrostatic repulsion of the electron cloud of the molecule through which it passes. In this case, the free electron is in the region of relatively low potential energy, i.e., in the intermediate position corresponding to the element of free volume in the fluid where it is stabilized by short-range repulsive forces.

Where in neurons could such non-electrolytic regions exist? As shown in Fig. 1, proteinaceous structures have apolar (hydrophobic) regions, for example in an enzymatic cleft (Mentre:2012). These proteinaceous structures found in thin cylindrical nonsynaptic spines of cortical interneurons are isolated from neuronal (synaptic) variability, especially thin sized nonsynaptic spines, approximately 0.09 μ m in diameter compared with the larger pyramidal neurons of the neocortex (Arellano:2007). Particularly, nonsynaptic spines with clearly absent synaptic-head like filopodia, containing cytoskeletal proteins bound to actin-filament (see Fig. 1). The nonpolar hydrophobic regions of proteins contain molecular dipole-bound electron densities that can undergo phase difference oscillations that differ from the polarized regions along actin filaments (Tuszynski:2004). Macro-quantum potential energy in nonsynaptic spines are theorized to carry intrinsic information through a nested hierarchy of nonconscious microprocesses. It is further suggested that ‘binding’ of intrinsic information would be en route for decoding in memory. The functional actin-filaments that are found in the cortical region near the membrane of neurons, while the actin-binding proteins that fill nonsynaptic spines were first proposed by (Woolf:2011) as a possible seat of biological consciousness.

Figure 1.

Schematic diagram illustrating (top left) a neuronal branchlet studded with spines and (top right) shows a nonsynaptic spine shaft containing cytoskeletal molecular proteins bound to actin-filament networks within the spine shaft of uniform length approximately 0.7 μ m and 100 nm in diameter. The quantized subspace is where pilot-waves originate at picometer scale ( 0.1 nm) within apolar hydrophobic regions of actin-binding proteins shown (bottom left) form clathrate-like structures with water molecules (adapted from Mentre:2012. The electron clouds at 10 pico-meter scale (bottom right) is an order of magnitude smaller than most chemistry transformations and measurements and therefore below physical chemistry.

Quantum chemistry underpins the so-called ‘quantum underground’ where consciousness originates (see (Craddock:2017) for a review). Due to inherent uncertainty in electron localization, the weakest type of Van der Waals force, the so-called London force, exhibit quantum effects and the resultant dipole oscillations (see (Hameroff:2008) for a review). London forces are quantum level instantaneous, but weak, induced dipole-induced dipole couplings, due to charge separation resulting in attractive Coulomb forces occurring between nonpolar π -electron resonance clouds of two or more neutral atoms, molecules or macromolecules. Nonpolar hydrophobicity signifies absence of electrostatic forces and hydrogen bonding. In nucleic acids and less commonly in proteins, ‘benzene-rings’ are stacked precisely on top of each other and hence support short-range interactions through London forces. It is only ring-like structures like ‘benzene-rings’ that can support oscillatory motion back and forth due to shared electron pairs between two carbons, based on free electrons in π -electron resonance clouds. (Hameroff:1982) postulated that London force dipoles in nonpolar hydrophobic regions of cytoplasmic proteins couple and oscillate coherently, and this coupling was suggested to be necessary for consciousness.

(Hameroff:1983) hypothesized that anesthetics bind in nonpolar hydrophobic regions of cytoskeletal proteins, dispersing endogenous London forces by inhibiting free electrons in π -electron resonance clouds. (Franks:1984) found that anesthetics acts directly within cytoskeletal proteins that bind to actin-filaments in spines (see also Kaech:1999). Actin-filaments are found along the plasma membrane of neurons and profusely fill dendritic spines (see (Hotulainen:2010) for a review). As a result, macroscopic description of subneuronal dynamics that can provide a novel physical attribution to ‘long-range’ coherence in biological systems (Preto:2016) where synchrony has been invoked as a neural basis for emergent consciousness (Hameroff:1982, Hameroff:1994, Tory:2018) as well as a precedence for unitary binding of consciousness (Crick:1994a) resulting in a unified conscious field (Searle:2017).

However, London forces cause dipole oscillations, but not necessarily the phase-differences of the oscillating molecular dipole-bound electrons succinctly referred to as quasi-free electron density distribution in proteins bound to actin filaments. Accordingly, an alternative explanation which is below physical chemistry is required. When using de Broglie-Bohm approach, we escape the need for binding and quantum coherency in signaling at the atomic scale. The formation of a macro-quantum state is a way of preventing against dissipation and could be the result of pairing molecular dipole-bound electrons of opposite spins, enabling the formation of strong bonds for atoms to form molecular ions. Spin pairing in molecules is dependent on the Pauli exclusion principle, yet molecular dipole-bound electrons can aid the formation of a macro-quantum state through quantum (electron) tunneling by way of a chiral potential (or selective guidance of electrons by the accompanying magnetic field) selecting spin polarizations in a dynamic network of atoms (Naaman:2016, Michaeli:2016, Banerjee-Ghosh:2018). which may give rise to more ‘electron smears’ without the need for quantum coherence.

We also assume that guidance waves and their resultant thermo-quantum fluctuations govern subtle internal energy leading to hierarchical thermodynamic transfer of information in the realm of preconscious. What is transferred from the macro-quantum realm to the classical realm is information (theoretic) entropy as thermo-qubits containing information on the phase relations between molecular dipole-bound electron clouds of multiple systems. A pattern of macro-quantum potential energy entails the transfer of thermo-qubits in the macro-quantum realm where the process of thermo-quantum fluctuations is driven by de Broglie ‘hidden’ thermodynamics (De:1970). Thermo-quantum fluctuations occur at quantum equilibrium as phase-differences of dipole-bound electrons due to active fields of electron clouds, which guides their motion involved in producing thermo-qubits. The information we are discussing is intrinsic in the sense that it remains ‘hidden’ from the operational explanations of cognitive capacities. It is neither quantum information nor integrated information, but interconnected ‘intrinsic’ information associated with the internal thermo-quantum fluctuations that arise due to guidance waves transferring thermo-quantum internal energy by means of the macro-quantum potential Grr:2009, (Nottale:2014). This internal energy in the brain originates beneath the realm of physical chemistry and is influenced by the ‘shape’ of the enveloping field density of molecular dipole-bound electrons associated with de Broglie ‘hidden’ thermodynamics.

How are the microprocesses actualized to achieve qualia? Qualia represents the content of thermo-qubits and it is obviously a function of the nonconscious microprocesses, but there is no evidence for qualia in cognitive processing. If we perceive a blue bird, then the blueness is a quale. Yet, the essence of a quale is not the color tone through cognitive processing, but rather it is the actualization of the potential ‘feeling’. Therefore, qualia are the phenomenal ‘feel’ of cognition, yet never a function of cognition. The notion of ‘feelings’ constitute a multitude of discrete atomic microfeels synonymous with the philosopher Alfred Whitehead’s spatiotemporal chains of ‘occasions of experience.’ The experienceability process entails a continuum of patterns of discrete atomic microfeels (‘qualia’) that constitutes a continuous stream of intrinsic information in the preconscious. But to include qualities of a being, qualia must become part of cognition, which must constitute 'cognized content'. The connection between preconscious and its cognized content is through hierarchical thermodynamic transfer of information culminating in thermo-qubits, which is a specific energy2(2 Specific energy is energy per unit mass) transfer in the macro-quantum realm where thermo-quantum fluctuations operate through de Broglie ’hidden’ thermodynamics De:1987. Thermo-qubits exist for λ L and fade because of thermal agitation when λ L . They get transferred within a nested hierarchy of microprocesses at equilibrium and dynamical macroprocesses out of equilibrium (Kosloff:2013).

From the viewpoint of irreversible thermodynamics of the human brain (Kirkaldy:1965), the nested hierarchy of nonconscious microprocesses are ‘open’ dissipative systems, in the sense that there is elimination of entropy across hierarchical levels (i.e., quasi-thermodynamic processes out of equilibrium). Therefore, entropic exchange between hierarchical levels is assumed to take place by way of hierarchical thermodynamic transfer of information. Hierarchical thermodynamics includes weakly nonequilibrium thermodynamics, also known as ‘quasi-equilibrium’ thermodynamics for systems close to equilibrium. Although the second-law of thermodynamics states that entropy and internal energy can only be created, but not eliminated in an ‘isolated’ thermodynamic system, supporting local-equilibrium conditions (Collell:2015), hierarchical thermodynamics purports quasi-thermodynamic conditions in the sense that there is elimination of entropy across hierarchical levels (i.e., spontaneous irreversible processes out of equilibrium). In other words, any microprocess consists of an operation cycle where the first stage of the entropic exchange between hierarchical levels is ‘closed’; thus, the thermodynamic transfer operates as an ‘isolated’ thermodynamic system and during the second stage the entropic exchange between hierarchical levels is ‘quasi-closed’; thus, the thermodynamic transfer operates as an ‘open’ dissipative system far from equilibrium (Del Castillo:2011).

The fundamental mechanism providing the change from potentiality to actuality may in principle be very similar for all nonconscious microprocesses involving hierarchic thermodynamic transfer of information (Mahler:2015). The de Broglie's 'hidden' thermodynamics (De:1970) plays a role in thermodynamic transfer of information across hierarchical levels. For example, entropic exchange is assumed to take place in dissipative structures far from equilibrium by way of transfer of thermo-quantum information as thermodynamic entropy. We now know that in such a system negative entropy can result, and order can emerge from disorder. For a wildly disordered system, large-scale order can emerge and stabilize, and the more chaotic the disorder, the greater the stability of the ordered patterns that emerge (Song:2018).

In a recent study, (Poznanski:2018) had used negentropy principle of information to bridge the explanatory gap (Levine:1983). This principle links decreases in information (theoretic) entropy with increases in thermal entropy (Brillouin:1953, Brillouin:1962). Therefore, this is not just a quantitative descriptor of the causal relations between measured events (subjective), but has a physical reality in terms of thermal entropy, which is an objective property of the brain (Collell:2015). The model states that brain-based consciousness is not solely based on quantum effects (Baars:2012, Hameroff:2014), but instead is a concomitant of dynamic patterns reflecting information (theoretic) entropy that is encoded from the lability in the phase differences of thermo-quantum fluctuations as thermo-qubits. Thermo-qubits carry intrinsic information through negentropic action within neurons which can be a cause of hidden communication.

In scientific foundations of neurology, consciousness is labile (Walshe:1972), but in clinical neurology, consciousness is often defined to be ‘on’ or ‘off’ as for example, when the patient is either asleep or in a coma and this observed by fMRI through coma-causing lesions in functional connectivity networks (Fischer:2016). The same applies to psychological perspectives or higher order theory of consciousness (Rosenthal:1997). However, such attempts at understanding consciousness are not grounded in the consciousness process as part of a spontaneous process. Theoretical work in this direction has been initiated by (Marchetti:2018) in which he details how consciousness is a ‘unique way’ of processing information, yet without demonstrating what this ‘unique way’ could be physically. As well, (Hameroff:2010) who first explored the idea of a ‘conscious pilot’ embodied in the activity of subneuronal structures forming a holoscope (i.e., cognized “wholes”). A very recent paper by (Schiffer:2019) points a way forward from the traditional medical definition of consciousness and puts forward the hypothesis that preconscious experienceability becomes subjective upon interaction with intrinsic information, while a further encounter with cognition leads to awareness thereby becoming full conscious experience (or the conscious Self).

In view of the above, we postulate a new theory on how the brain encodes consciousness based on ‘negentropic entanglement’ of intrinsic information. Negentropic entanglement binds nonconscious entities to ‘potential’ conscious entities, temporally, thus acting as an integrator of thermo-qubits conveying ‘meaning’ expressed at the fundamental level, arising at the atomic scale of matter from de Broglie ‘hidden’ thermodynamics. The ‘meaning’ of negentropic entanglement is ascribed to the negentropic action or experiential flow of macro-quantum potential energy in a nested hierarchy of nonconscious microprocesses as thermo-qubits reflecting internal thermo-quantum fluctuations associated with the lability in the phase differences of the molecular dipole-bound electron oscillations.

2. Methods

Quantum chemistry governs the behavior of electrons that are bound to atomic nuclei resulting in stable inter-atomic bonds in the formation of molecules. The guidance wave theory is at the atomic scale yet independent of quantum chemistry. A wave function has characteristics of a macroscopic quantum state referred to as ‘quantum-like’ (Gould:1995). It is not the standard wave function of quantum mechanics, used to measure potentialities, but describing the passage of a potentiality to actuality based on the wave function’s averaged statistical characteristics. The wave function ( ψ ) is dimensionless and describes the instantaneous state of the enveloping ‘active’ field density of molecular dipole-bound electrons modeled by the macro-quantum wave equation:

i γ ψ τ = - γ 2 2 m 2 ψ + U Ψ + ε | Ψ 2 | Ψ
where ε is a parameter that regulates the strength of the nonlinearity in units of [energy], m is the mass of electrons in units of [mass] and the action parameter ( γ ) carries dimensions of [energy][time]. This is known as the modified nonlinear Schrödinger equation or nonlinear macro-quantum wave equation. Like the so-called the Gross-Pitaevskii equation (Barenghi:2016) that includes interactions through the addition of an interaction potential term | ψ 2 | ψ may give more insight on the individual electron cloud interactions. Eq.2 when ϵ =0 is simplified to the linear Schrödinger equation and can be solved by substituting the Madelung transformation: ψ = ρ ( x , t ) e i S γ into (Eq.2), upon separating the imaginary and real parts. The real part describes how the ‘shape’ of the enveloping field density of molecular dipole-bound electrons is represented by the phase differences of the oscillating molecular dipole-bound electrons expressed in terms of the Hamilton-Jacobi equation (Gould:1995):

s t + 1 2 m ( S ) 2 + U + Q = 0
where S = i 2 γ ln ψ * ψ is the action function of the phase differences of oscillating molecular dipole-bound electrons in units of [energy][time], φ * is the complex conjugate of the wave function and is the gradient (in one-dimension x ). The constant of inverse proportionality ( ν ) in the relation γ = ν / S carries dimensions of [length] [energy] [time]. The constant of inverse proportionality ( ν ) between the ‘action’ parameter ( γ ) in units of [energy][time] and the gradient of the action function ( S ) in units of [energy][time]/[length]:

S = i γ ( 1 Ψ * Ψ * x - 1 Ψ Ψ x )
The action function is under the action of two ‘potentials’: (i) the classical potential energy function U(x,t) in units of [energy] and (ii) the macro-quantum potential energy in units of [energy]:

Q ( x , t ) = - 1 2 m γ 2 2 ρ ( x , t ) ρ ( x , t )
where ρ ( x , t ) is the enveloping field density distribution (dimensionless) , x is the length scale and 2 is the Laplacian (in one-dimension 2 χ 2 ). The macro-quantum potential (Q) like the quantum potential (Bohm:1990) is an emergent potential that is not explicitly given in Eq.3 until the solution of Eq.2 is found via the Born rule, linking the amplitude of the wave function to the enveloping field density distribution: ρ ( x , t ) = | ψ | 2 . The Born rule implies quantum equilibrium conditions. Note: The macro-quantum potential applies to a single electron density cloud and it is not a super macro-quantum potential which applies in the case of several electron density clouds and how they interact together. This is a simplification of the model since we ignore such interactions between electrons in density clouds and between multiple electron density clouds. If we introduce the simple case of a static classical potential energy with a unitary value U=1 and letting ε = 0 then the solution of Eq.2 is readily found, viz.

Ψ ( x , t ) = Ψ 0 ( x , t ) e - i γ t
and enveloping field density distribution ρ ( x , t ) = | ψ | 2 where ψ 0 (x,t) satisfies the macro-quantum reduced wave equation:

i γ ψ 0 t = - γ 2 2 2 Ψ 0
Eq.7 ignores the effects of the classical potential energy U=0 and considers solely the quantum effects of the molecular dipole-bound electron densities.

The separation of variables method yields a solution of Eq.7 in terms of spatial region of length (average molecular dipole-bound electron distance) L, subject to Dirichlet boundary conditions (Pribram:1991):

ψ o ( x , t ) = ( 1 L ) n = 1 c n e - 2 γ i ( γ 2 L 2 π 2 n 2 t - γ L π x )
where c n are Fourier coefficients independent of time in units of [length]. In the ontological interpretation of quantum mechanics, a ‘pilot-wave’ guides the enveloping field density of molecular dipole-bound electrons whose ‘shape’ determines their phase differences of the thermo-quantum fluctuations in a way, so it also acts as an ‘information channel’ through a context-dependent energy redistribution (Hiley:2002, Sbitnev:2009, Dennis:2015). Moreover, Q conveys meaning as an information channel and as a quantum ‘corrector’ of the total energy. The kinetic energy is 1 2 m ( S ) 2 and from Eq.3 the total energy is - S t .

With Born’s rule and application of the chain and product rules, Eq.5 becomes:

Q ( x , t ) = - 1 4 m γ 2 [ 2 ρ ρ - 1 2 ( ρ ) 2 ρ 2 ]
and together with ρ / ρ = ( ln ρ ) Eq.9 reduces to:

Q ( x . t ) = - γ 2 8 m [ ( ln ρ ) 2 ] - γ 2 4 m [ 2 ( ln ρ ) ]
Intrinsic information is not Shannonian, but Fisherian (in the sense of uncertainty), and observer-independent thus it is computable. The non-computability in the sense of Gödelian information (Cicurel:2015) is a kind of intrinsic representation of the brain within cognition, representing intrinsic information via uncertainty in the brain. In the context of thermodynamic effects, Q is proportional to Fisher information (theoretic) entropy (measure of the uncertainty of data in an ‘information channel’) and the negentropic force can be explicitly determined from the gradient of the local Boltzmann thermal entropy (cf., Tsekov:2012). The negentropic force is due to thermo-quantum internal energy (Q) as per de Broglie ‘hidden’ thermodynamics arising from the microscopic scale of matter. In view of the negentropy principle of information (Brillouin:1953, Brillouin:1962), the negentropic action reflects a ‘consciousness guidance’ because information (theoretic) entropy is subjective at the scale of measurement. Therefore, Q in the context of thermo-quantum fluctuations, produces negentropic action, which is not a mechanical action but simply the action of S where negentropic action can be channeled through the negentropic force.

The quantum force F Q = - Q has been evaluated based on the de Broglie-Bohm theory:

F Q = Υ 2 4 m ρ 2 [ ρ 3 ρ - 1 2 ( ρ . ρ ) - ρ ( 2 ρ - ρ . ρ ρ ) ]
The negentropic action representing experiential flow of specific energy that results in a negentropic force can also be explicitly represented by the gradient of the local Boltzmann thermal entropy S Q (Tsekov:2012). Defining the Boltzmann thermal entropy (Sbitnev:2009) as a logarithmic function S Q = - 1 2 ln ( ρ ) and Eq.10 becomes:

Q ( x , t ) = - γ 2 2 m [ ( S Q ) 2 ] + γ 2 2 m 2 S Q
Here the first-term on the RHS is viewed as the macro-quantum ‘corrector’ of the kinetic energy term and the second-term on the RHS influences the classical potential energy term U in Eq.2. The kinetic energy becomes 1 2 m ( S ) 2 - γ 2 2 m [ ( S Q ) 2 ] and the classical potential energy becomes U + γ 2 2 m 2 S Q . This implies that the kinetic energy of the oscillating molecular dipole-bound electrons contains a negentropic term. Note: ( S ) 2 has unit of ({[energy][time]/[length]}) 2 = [mass][energy]. A mean approximation of the negentropic force determined directly by Eq.12 through F Q = - Q is responsible for the of phase differences of the oscillating molecular dipole-bound electrons (cf. Dennis:2015; Heifetz:2016).

3. Results

The negentropic force can be explicitly represented by the gradient of the macro-quantum potential energy F Q = - Q , where Q is expressed by Eq.12 which is shown in Fig. 2. The real component indicates changes to the average phase difference of the oscillating molecular dipole-bound electrons, while the imaginary component signifies the movement of the phase differences from their average values. The sense of a negentropic force specifies the direction (positive or negative) in which the force moves along the line of action, which in Fig. 2 is shown that the real component of F Q is both spatially positive and negative in amplitude. A negative amplitude of F Q indicates the direction is reversed to the mean approximation. This implies that zero amplitudes reflect coherence, while non-zero amplitudes, designate incoherency necessary for the negentropic action (or experiential flow of thermo-quantum internal energy that results in a negentropic force) to be encoded. The negentropic action representing experiential flow of specific energy that results in a negentropic force appears to be on-going without dissipating, defining what is meant by negentropic entanglement. The movement from the average values has certain regions where F Q is zero. However, the average values are never zero which is an indication that F Q is continuous supporting the concept of negentropic entanglement.

Figure 2.

The mean approximation of the negentropic force in units of Newton per unit mass as a function of space resulting from the macro-quantum potential energy (Q) for (a) L = 1, t = 0.1, γ = 1.0 (b) L = 0.1, t = 0.01, γ = 0.01. and (c) L = 1.5, t = 0.5, γ = 2. Real component is shown in blue and imaginary component is shown in red. The values of the parameters were arbitrarily chosen.

A temporal variation in the mean approximation of the negentropic force is shown in Fig. 3. The nonzero-real values of F Q indicate that mean approximation of the negentropic force can be used to encode changes to the average phase differences, while a non-zero imaginary component signifies the fluctuation from this mean-approximation of F Q . The sense of continuity with time in both real and imaginary component of F Q comes about from the phase differences of thermo-quantum fluctuations guided by the macro-quantum potential energy. The mean approximation of the negentropic force as given by the non-zero real value of F Q signify the phase differences of the oscillating molecular dipole-bound electrons. They can differ from coupled molecular dipoles that oscillate between different orientations associated with endogenous London forces over long distances.

Figure 3.

The sense of the negentropic force in units of Newton per unit mass as a function of time resulting from the macro-quantum potential energy (Q) for (a) L = 1, γ = 1.0, x = 0.1 (b) L = 0.1, γ = 0.01,x = 0.025 and (c) L = 1.5, γ = 2, x = 0.5. Real component is shown as a continuous line (blue) and imaginary component is shown as a dashed line (red). The values of the parameters were arbitrarily chosen.

The spatial variation in the mean approximation of the negentropic force at a smaller scale to Fig. 2 is shown in Fig.4. The amplitude of F Q depends on the typical length scale (see Eq.1). The smaller the length scale the greater is the magnitude of negentropic force. When L = 0.1 (b) the amplitude is significantly greater compared when L = 1 (a) and L = 1.5 (c). We can surmise from this result that at smaller length scales the quantum processes prevail to reveal significant thermo-quantum fluctuations, while at larger length scales, less significant thermo-quantum fluctuations occur. The ‘consciousness code’ arises when quantum effects are not negligible and phase differences of thermo-quantum fluctuations of the oscillating molecular dipole-bound electrons are evident. When the thermal de Broglie wavelength ( λ ) is much smaller than the average molecular dipole-bound electron distance (L), the fluctuations can be treated classically as thermal fluctuations. On the other hand, when the thermal de Broglie wavelength ( λ ) is on the order of or larger than the average molecular dipole-bound electron distance (L), quantum effects will dominate, and the fluctuations must be treated non-classically as thermo-quantum fluctuations.

Figure 4.

The sense of the negentropic force in units of Newton per unit mass as a function of space resulting from the macro-quantum potential energy (Q) for (a) L = 1, γ = 1.0, t = 0.1 (b) L = 0.1, γ = 0.01, t = 0.01 and (c) L = 1.5, γ = 2.0, t = 0.5. Real component is shown as a continuous line (blue) and imaginary component is shown as a dashed line (red). The values of the parameters were arbitrarily chosen.

A relation between consciousness and negative entropy was proposed by (Song:2018) where the latter was declared as a ‘visible image of invisible consciousness’. The negentropic action can be channeled through the negentropy information principle as a ‘consciousness guidance’ consisting of dynamical patterns reflecting thermo-qubits. The ‘consciousness guidance’ is labile. Both real and imaginary components of F Q have unique patterns that may signify informational content influenced by the ‘shape’ of the enveloping ‘active’ field density (cf. Figs. 3-4). This continuous real component of the mean approximation of the negentropic force points to continuous streams of information (theoretic) entropy (subjectivity) that are encoded in diverse way from the lability in the phase differences of thermo-quantum fluctuations. Due to application of the negentropy information principle, a ‘consciousness guidance’ arises from the gradient of the local Boltzmann thermal entropy ( S Q ). The quantum ‘corrector’ of the kinetic energy - γ 2 2 m [ ( S Q ) 2 ] of the oscillating molecular dipole-bound electrons contributes to the ‘consciousness guidance’ since information (theoretic) entropy is subjective at the scale of measurement. The ‘consciousness guidance’ is encoded through the non-zero real component of the mean approximation of the negentropic force to form a ‘consciousness code’.

4. Discussion

We clearly advocate that internal energy in the brain has a capacity for ‘feeling’ or experienceability without any claim that such preconscious episodes are a fundamental property of nature, providing the quality of that which is felt, i.e., a quale. This is against the ‘anthropic principle’ that claims consciousness is fundamental (cf. panpsychism). Panpsychist materialism portrays matter as inert as well as consciousness and therefore there is no other way to account for consciousness.

Our work based on panexperiential materialism considers matter not to be inert, but fluid-like, manifesting its influence at the atomic scale of matter through the action of guidance waves that originate from properties of electron clouds in brains. Thus, panexperiential physicalism is not mutually incompatible to materialist physicalism and hence what we call ‘panexperiential materialism’, which is causally efficacious in the preconscious. The noninertness of matter due to experiential flow of internal energy in the preconscious is associated with a nested hierarchy of nonconscious microprocesses, which is actualized as a continuum of patterns of discrete atomic ‘microfeels’(‘qualia’) (Holmgren:2014). Panexperientialist physicalism (Griffin:1997) considers actualized differences in energy to be the cause of consciousness. There is, however, a distinct difference between the notion of conscious experience and what panexperientialism claims to be preconscious experienceability.

The idea that if conscious processes are indeed physical processes, then there is something it is like, intrinsically, to undergo certain physical processes (Nagel:1974). (Pepperell:2018) argued for consciousness as a physical process caused by the organization of energy in the brain. Accordingly, it is specific energy transfer described in terms of actualized differences that supervene on neuronal activity. Although there is nothing in the brain that supervenes on the physical brain processes, nonconscious processes are physical brain processes too, but at a different hierarchical level in accordance with nonreductive physicalism the supervenience is ‘unpacked ’through hierarchical thermodynamic transfer of information.

Consciousness according to “biological naturalism” has no causal power (Searle:2007, Searle:2017). Therefore, transmutation of thermo-quantum fluctuations to normal-level neural signaling (MacGregor:2006) is inconsistent with quantum indeterminacy principle (Lewis:2006). As well, based on the indeterminacy principle, thermo-qubits cannot be amplified by electromagnetic fields interacting with cognition. This is because polarized regions associated with cognitive neural signaling are completely omniscient of guidance waves, whose abode is hypothesized to be in nonpolar hydrophobic regions of cytoskeletal proteins bound to actin filaments. Therefore, our theory is not a dual-aspect interactionist theory of mind in which the mind is an energetic source and the mind-brain interaction occurs through a binding of an electromagnetic field.

The higher phase of consciousness expressed through conscious perception and decoded in memory remains to be explored. The model supports the pioneering ideas of mathematical biologist Alfred Lotka’s conceptualization of consciousness not evolving from lower cell to higher cell organisms given an “elementary flash of consciousness may be a native of matter” (Lotka:1956), but rather it is the evolution of organisms that has allowed consciousness to be decoded in memory and therefore expressed. Preconscious experienceability is not expressed through perception like conscious perception must be. Thus, the notion of subjectivity comes from the intrinsic information and not from outside of the brain. This intrinsicness does not evolve, but is inherent in qubit-like properties of electron clouds. For this reason, we have advanced panexperiential materialism, where biological evolution is bounded by a materialistic pre-existence of the physical nature of subjective experience. That is, the popular notion of emergence of consciousness has no precedence in the solution of the mind-brain problem.

5. Conclusion

In this paper, we described how the internal energy processing is encoded to form a ‘consciousness code’ through the negentropy principle of information. In accordance with panexperiential materialism, the experiential flow of macro-quantum potential energy was realized through the nonzero real component to the mean approximation of the negentropic force. Such negentropic action was continuous in terms of its spatial distribution implying ‘binding’ of intrinsic information that we defined to be ‘negentropic entanglement’. By way of negentropic entanglement of hierarchical thermodynamic transfer of information as thermo-qubits, we have shown the essential process of experienceability in the preconscious.

Acknowledgement

We thank Alex Hankey, Jan Holmgren and Valeriy Sbitnev for detailed comments. Phichai Youplao for technical assistance. Funding support from UTM (FRGS-4F891) is greatly appreciated (J.A).

Conflict of Interest

The authors declare that there is no conflict of interest regarding the publication of this article.

References
[1]
Arellano , J. I ., Espinosa , A ., Fairen , A ., Yuste , R . and DeFelipe , J . ( 2007) Non-synaptic dendritic spines in neocortex . Neuroscience 145 , 464 - 469 . 10.1016/j.neuroscience.2006.12.015 17240073 3f39f86e3e45d22006a5fdb31480826e http%3A%2F%2Feuropepmc.org%2Fabstract%2Fmed%2F17240073 http://europepmc.org/abstract/med/17240073
[2]
Baars , B. J . and Edelman , D. B . ( 2012) Consciousness, biology and quantum hypotheses . Physics of Life Reviews 9 , 285 - 294 . 10.1016/j.plrev.2012.07.001 22925839 6eaa5b63aebf7db876a3e0ec386a4dbe http%3A%2F%2Feuropepmc.org%2Fabstract%2FMED%2F22925839 http://europepmc.org/abstract/MED/22925839
[3]
Banerjee-Ghosh , K ., Dor , O.B ., Tassinari , F ., Capua , E ., Yochelis , S ., Capua , A ., Yang , S-H ., , Parkin , S, S. P ., Sarkar , S ., Kronik , L ., Baczewski , L. T ., Naaman , R . and Paltiel , Y . ( 2018) Separation of enantiomers by their enantiospecific interaction with achiral magnetic substrates . Science 360 , 1331 - 1334 . 10.1126/science.aar4265 29748324 e9e723d0123009d6d1a2a56f00449987 http%3A%2F%2Fwww.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov%2Fpubmed%2F29748324 http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/29748324
[4]
Barenghi , C. F . and Parker , N. G . ( 2016) A Primer on Quantum Fluids. Springer , Berlin.
[5]
Beck , F. and Eccles , J. C . ( 1992) Quantum aspects of brain activity and the role of consciousness . Proceedings of the National Academy of Science (USA) 89 , 11357 - 11361 . 10.1007/978-3-642-49224-2_9 1333607 cf05f2c02f6ee641c1f5e449008de4ac http%3A%2F%2Fwww.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov%2Fpubmed%2F1333607 http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/1333607
[6]
Bohm , D. J . ( 1952) A suggested interpretation of the quantum theory in terms of hidden variables . Physical Review 85 , 166 - 193 . 10.1103/PhysRev.85.166 80a38df60edb99e816898577d1ddd66e http%3A%2F%2Fwww.ams.org%2Fmathscinet-getitem%3Fmr%3D46288 http://www.ams.org/mathscinet-getitem?mr=46288
[7]
Bohm , D. J . ( 1990) A new theory of the relationship of mind and matter . Philosophical Psychology 3 , 271 - 286 . 10.1080/09515089008573004 6a8f8f23d6711fb149e0035c3e3d9167 http%3A%2F%2Fpsycnet.apa.org%2Frecord%2F1991-14121-001 http://psycnet.apa.org/record/1991-14121-001
[8]
Brillouin , L . ( 1953) The negentropy principle of information . Journal of Applied Physics 24 , 1152 - 1163 . 10.1063/1.1721463 9d5ed95f43b402714f4df2b9ea3f7711 http%3A%2F%2Fieeexplore.ieee.org%2Fxpls%2Fabs_all.jsp%3Farnumber%3D5120546 http://ieeexplore.ieee.org/xpls/abs_all.jsp?arnumber=5120546
[9]
Brillouin , L .( 1962) Science and Information Theory. Academic Press , New York .
[10]
Cicurel , R . and Nicolelis , M . ( 2015) The Relativistic Brain: How It Works and Why It cannot be Simulated by a Turing Machine. Kios Press, Sao Paulo .
[11]
Collell , G . and Fauquet , J . ( 2015) Brain activity and cognition: a connection from thermodynamics and information theory . Frontiers in Psychology 6 , 818 .
[12]
Craddock , T. J. A ., Hameroff , S. R . and Tuszynski , J. A . ( 2017) The ‘quantum underground’: where life and consciousness originate . In, R.R.Poznanski, J.A. Tuszynski and T.E. Feinberg (eds) Biophysics of Consciousness: A Foundational Approach. World Scientific, Singapore .
[13]
Crick , F. H. C . ( 1994 a) The Astonishing Hypothesis. London , Simon & Schuster .
[14]
Crick , F. H. C ( 1994 b) Interview on the astonishing hypothesis . Journal of Consciousness. Studies 1 , 17 - 24 .
[15]
Del Castillo , L. F . and Vera-Cruz , P . ( 2011) Thermodynamic formulation of living systems and their evolution . Journal of Modern Physics 2 , 379 - 391 .
[16]
Dennis , G ., de Gosson , M. A . and Hiley , B. J . ( 2015) Bohm’s quantum potential as an internal energy . Physics Letters A 379 , 1224 - 1227 . 10.1016/j.physleta.2015.02.038 ee397dc60976cc1fdd3e9b55087212bc http%3A%2F%2Fwww.sciencedirect.com%2Fscience%2Farticle%2Fpii%2FS037596011500211X http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S037596011500211X
[17]
de Broglie , L . ( 1970) The reinterpretation of wave mechanics . Foundations of Physics 1 , 5 - 15 .
[18]
de Broglie , L . ( 1987) The reinterpretation of quantum mechanics by the double solution theory . Annales de la Fondation Louis de Broglie 12 , 1 - 23 .
[19]
Fischer , D. B ., Boes , A. D ., Demertzi , A ., Evrard , H. C ., Laureys , S ., Edlow , B. L ., Liu , H ., Saper , C. B ., Pascual-Leone , A ., Fox , M. D . and Geerling , J. C . ( 2016) A human brain network derived from coma-causing brainstem lesions . Neurology 87 , 2427 - 2434 . 10.1212/WNL.0000000000003404 5177681 a7019ba99d1170bf86396e25b143cec3 http%3A%2F%2Fwww.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov%2Fpubmed%2F27815400 http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/27815400
[20]
Franks , N. P . and Lieb , W. R . ( 1984) Do general anaesthetics act by competitive binding to specific receptors? Nature 310 , 599 - 601 .
[21]
Georgiev , D . ( 2007) Falsifications of Hameroff-Penrose Orch OR model of consciousness and novel avenues for development of quantum mind theory . NeuroQuantology 5 , 145 - 174 .
[22]
Gould , L. I . ( 1995) Quantum dynamics and neural dynamics: analogies between the formalisms of Bohm and Pribram . In, J. King and K.H. Pribram (eds.) Scale in Conscious Experience: Is the Brain Too Important To Be Left to Specialists to Study? Lawrence Erlbaum, New Jersey .
[23]
Griffin , D. R . ( 1997) Panexperientialist physicalism . Journal of Consciousness Studies 4 , 248 - 268 .
[24]
Grössing , G . ( 2009) On the thermodynamic origin of the quantum potential . Physica A 388 , 811 - 823 . 10.1016/j.physa.2008.11.033 c50ac1b34ba03f0128fdb782a7939cac http%3A%2F%2Fwww.sciencedirect.com%2Fscience%2Farticle%2Fpii%2FS0378437108009758 http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0378437108009758
[25]
Hameroff , S. R . ( 1994) Quantum coherence in microtubules: a neural basis for emergent consciousness . Journal of Consciousness Studies 1 , 91 - 118 . cd7816eb0a6875f5ca24d2ea03edbf7b http%3A%2F%2Fwww.ingentaconnect.com%2Fcontent%2Fimp%2Fjcs%2F1994%2F00000001%2F00000001%2Fart00008 http://www.ingentaconnect.com/content/imp/jcs/1994/00000001/00000001/art00008
[26]
Hameroff , S. R . ( 2008) That’s Life! The geometry of $\pi$ electron resonance clouds . In, D. Abbott, P.C.W. Davis and A.K. Pati (eds) Quantum Aspects of Life. World Scientific Publishers, Singapore .
[27]
Hameroff , S. R . ( 2010) The ‘conscious pilot’- dendritic synchrony moves through the brain to mediate consciousness . Journal of Biological Physics 36 , 71 - 93 . 10.1007/s10867-009-9148-x 19669425 2265281bf1245dc556c7b978268d1981 http%3A%2F%2Fpubmedcentralcanada.ca%2Fpmcc%2Farticles%2FPMC2791805%2F http://pubmedcentralcanada.ca/pmcc/articles/PMC2791805/
[28]
Hameroff , S. R . and Penrose , R . ( 1996 a) Conscious events as orchestrated space-time selections . Journal of Consciousness Studies 3 , 36 - 53 . 10.1016/S0735-1097(13)61388-1 9f1329ea61e3df6032648ed428d5b594 http%3A%2F%2Fwww.clinicalkey.com%2Fcontent%2Fplay%2F1-s2.0-S0735109713613881 http://www.clinicalkey.com/content/play/1-s2.0-S0735109713613881
[29]
Hameroff , S. R . and Penrose , R . ( 1996 b) Orchestrated reduction of quantum coherence in brain microtubules: a model for consciousness . Mathematics and Computers in Simulation 40 , 453 - 480 . 10.1016/0378-4754(96)80476-9 92192fc55fb12d5da53fe43efbfa76f8 http%3A%2F%2Fwww.sciencedirect.com%2Fscience%2Farticle%2Fpii%2F0378475496804769 http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/0378475496804769
[30]
Hameroff , S. R . and Penrose , R . ( 2017) Consciousness in the universe: An updated review of the “Orch OR’ theory . In, R.R.Poznanski, J.A. Tuszynski & T.E. Feinberg (eds) Biophysics of Consciousness: A Foundational Approach. World Scientific, Singapore . 10.1016/j.plrev.2013.08.002 24070914 fb9f53f7d626be8f8f1df5d8abdb8ce5 http%3A%2F%2Fwww.europepmc.org%2Fabstract%2FMED%2F24070914 http://www.europepmc.org/abstract/MED/24070914
[31]
Hamerroff , S. R ., Watt , R. C ., Borel , J. D . and Carlson , G . ( 1982) General anesthetics directly inhibit electron mobility: dipole dispersion theory of anesthetic action . Physiological Chemistry and Physics 14 , 183 - 187 .
[32]
Hameroff , S. R . and Watt , R. C . ( 1983) Do anesthetics act by altering electron mobility? Anesthesia & Analgesia 62 , 936 - 940 . 10.1213/00000539-198310000-00015 6614526 37ad592fd436ca539ed73fa64910d73e http%3A%2F%2Feuropepmc.org%2Fabstract%2FMED%2F6614526 http://europepmc.org/abstract/MED/6614526
[33]
Hameroff , S. R ., Craddock , T. J. A . and Tuszynski , J. A . ( 2014) Quantum effects in the understanding of consciousness . Journal of Integrative Neuroscience. 13 , 229 - 252 . 10.1142/S0219635214400093 25012711 01ba9a0eb64fe28076535111720bad33 http%3A%2F%2Fwww.worldscientific.com%2Fdoi%2Fabs%2F10.1142%2FS0219635214400093 http://www.worldscientific.com/doi/abs/10.1142/S0219635214400093
[34]
Hotulainen , P . and Hoogenraad , C. C . ( 2010) Actin in dendritic spines: connecting dynamics to function . Journal of Cell Biology 189 , 619 - 629 .
[35]
Heifetz , E ., Tsekov , R ., Cohen , E . and Nussinov , Z . ( 2016) On entropy production in the madelung fluid and the role of Bohm’s potential in classical diffusion . Foundations of Physics 46 , 815 - 824 . 10.1007/s10701-016-0003-1 7f1dd3f453ab3ba4231ec06aac2549ca http%3A%2F%2Flink.springer.com%2Farticle%2F10.1007%2Fs10701-016-0003-1 http://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s10701-016-0003-1
[36]
Hiley , B. J . ( 2002) From the Heisenberg picture to Bohm: a new perspective on active information and its relation to Shannon information . In, A. Khrennikov (ed.) Quantum Theory: Reconsideration of Foundations. Växjä University Press, Sweden .
[37]
Holmgren , J . ( 2014) Natural evolution and human consciousness . Mens Sana Monographs 12 , 127 - 138 . 10.4103/0973-1229.130322 4037892 e0556aaf1d0c3a6001dee3d7fcf9c210 http%3A%2F%2Fpubmedcentralcanada.ca%2Fpmcc%2Farticles%2FPMC4037892%2F http://pubmedcentralcanada.ca/pmcc/articles/PMC4037892/
[38]
Kaech , S., Brinkhaus, H . and Matus , A . ( 1999) Volatile anesthetics block actin-based motility in dendritic spines . Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences (USA) 96 , 10433 - 10437 . 10.1073/pnas.96.18.10433 10468626 7b758e97e881619767e2ebc88ff8b99c http%3A%2F%2Fonlinelibrary.wiley.com%2Fresolve%2Freference%2FPMED%3Fid%3D10468626
[39]
Kirkaldy , J. S . ( 1965) Thermodynamics of the human brain . Biophysical Journal 5 , 981 - 986 .
[40]
Kosloff , R . ( 2013) Quantum thermodynamics: a dynamical viewpoint . Entropy 15 , 2100 - 2128 .
[41]
Lewis , E. R . and MacGregor , R. J . ( 2006) On indeterminism, chaos, and small number particle systems in the brain . Journal of Integrative Neuroscience 5 , 223 - 247 . 10.1142/S0219635206001112 16783870 93a95ddba48fbeef0913d79f25ebbdfd http%3A%2F%2Fwww.worldscientific.com%2Fdoi%2Fabs%2F10.1142%2FS0219635206001112 http://www.worldscientific.com/doi/abs/10.1142/S0219635206001112
[42]
Levine , J . ( 1983) Materialism and qualia: the explanatory gap . Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 64 , 354 - 361 . 10.1111/j.1468-0114.1983.tb00207.x fee964e1b30aa900891c22efbbfe49d7 http%3A%2F%2Fonlinelibrary.wiley.com%2Fdoi%2F10.1111%2Fj.1468-0114.1983.tb00207.x%2Fpdf http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/j.1468-0114.1983.tb00207.x/pdf
[43]
Lotka , A. J . ( 1956) Elements of Mathematical Biology. Dover, New York .
[44]
Michaeli , K ., Kantor-Uriel , N ., Naaman , R . and Waldeck , D. H . ( 2016) The electron’s spin and molecular chirality—how are they related and how do they affect life processes? Chemistry Society Reviews 45 , 6478 . 10.1039/c6cs00369a 27734046 a02a1a3e1ce7f1dd84dd86ce5ac7c175 http%3A%2F%2Fwww.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov%2Fpubmed%2F27734046 http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/27734046
[45]
Mahler , G . ( 2015) Quantum Thermodynamics: Energy and Information Flow at the Nanoscale. CRC Press, Boca Raton, Fl .
[46]
MacGregor , R. J . ( 2006) Quantum mechanics and brain uncertainty . Journal of Integrative Neuroscience 5 , 373 - 380 . 10.1142/S0219635206001215 17125159 389748f6dda203f80329755f125d3a2d http%3A%2F%2Feuropepmc.org%2Fabstract%2FMED%2F17125159 http://europepmc.org/abstract/MED/17125159
[47]
Marchetti , G . ( 2018) Consciousness: a unique way of processing information . Cognitive Processing 19 , 435 - 464 . 10.1007/s10339-018-0855-8 29423666 e993edfd22cd9eacb5a6408f4fc6ef47 http%3A%2F%2Fwww.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov%2Fpubmed%2F29423666 http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/29423666
[48]
Meijer , D. K. F . and Geesink , H. J. H . ( 2018) Guided folding of life’s proteins in integrate cells with holographic memory and GM-biophysical steering . Open Journal of Biophysics 8 , 117 - 154 .
[49]
Mentre , P . ( 2012) Water in the orchestration of the cell machinery. Some misunderstandings: A short review . Journal of Biological Physics 38 , 13 - 26 .
[50]
Naaman , R . ( 2016) Chirality—Beyond the structural effects . Israel Journal of Chemistry 56 , 1010 - 1015 . 10.1002/ijch.201600102 830ed781938189619b9ad05f40c20dc7 http%3A%2F%2Fonlinelibrary.wiley.com%2Fdoi%2F10.1002%2Fijch.201600102%2Fpdf http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/ijch.201600102/pdf
[51]
Nagel , T . ( 1974) What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review 83 , 435 - 450 . 10.2307/2183914 00cadf289eb25d7170b4cd1122bf42bc http%3A%2F%2Fwww.jstor.org%2Fstable%2F2183914 http://www.jstor.org/stable/2183914
[52]
Nottale , L . ( 2014) Macroscopic quantum-type potentials in theoretical systems biology . Cells 1 , 1 - 35 . 10.3390/cells3010001 24709901 fdb8b45ab20b5be36064bae12f277f60 http%3A%2F%2Fpubmedcentralcanada.ca%2Fpmcc%2Farticles%2Fpmid%2F24709901 http://pubmedcentralcanada.ca/pmcc/articles/pmid/24709901
[53]
Pepperell , R . ( 2018) Consciousness as a physical process caused by the organization of energy in the brain . Frontiers in Psychology 9 : 2091 . 4b2ba5619af3c6d7071eaf0bdb8a35bd http%3A%2F%2Farxiv.org%2Fabs%2F1804.10508v3
[54]
Poznanski , R. R ., Cacha , L. A ., Latif , A. Z. A ., Salleh , S. H ., Ali , J ., Yupapin , P ., Tuszynski , J. A . and Tengku , M. A . ( 2018) Spontaneous potentiality as formative cause of thermo-quantum consciousness . Journal of Integrative Neuroscience 17 , 371 - 385 .
[55]
Preto , J . ( 2016) Classical investigation of long-range coherence in biological systems . Chaos 26 , 123116-1-13. 10.1063/1.4971963 28039969 c35b2f5ae19356b6829d32417ca0f4e4 http%3A%2F%2Feuropepmc.org%2Fabstract%2FMED%2F28039969 http://europepmc.org/abstract/MED/28039969
[56]
Pribram , K. H . ( 1991) Brain and Perception: Holonomy and Structure in Figural Processing. Lawrence Erlbaum, New Jersey .
[57]
Rosenthal , D. M . ( 1997) A theory of consciousness . In, N. Block, O. Flanagan and G. Güzeldere (eds) The Nature of Consciousness. MIT Press, Camb., MA .
[58]
Schiffer , F . ( 2019) The physical nature of subjective experience and its interaction with the brain . Medical Hypotheses 125 , 57 - 69 .
[59]
Searle , J. R . ( 2007) Biological naturalism . In M. Velmans and S. Schneider, eds The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness. Blackwell, Oxford .
[60]
Searle , J. R . ( 2017) Addressing the hard problem of consciousness . In, R.R.Poznanski, J.A. Tuszynski & T.E. Feinberg (eds) Biophysics of Consciousness: A Foundational Approach. World Scientific, Singapore .
[61]
Sbitnev , V. I . ( 2009) Bohmian trajectories and the path integral paradigm: complexified Lagrangian mechanics . International Journal of Bifurcation and Chaos 19 , 2335 - 2346 . 10.1142/S0218127409024104 44b89afd9af189c7c2a2a97151e2cbb7 http%3A%2F%2Fwww.worldscientific.com%2Fdoi%2Fabs%2F10.1142%2FS0218127409024104 http://www.worldscientific.com/doi/abs/10.1142/S0218127409024104
[62]
Song , D . ( 2018) Visualization of information . NeuroQuantology 16 , 32 - 36 .
[63]
Tory Toole , J ., Kurian , P . and Craddock , T. J. A . ( 2018) Coherent energy transfer and the potential implications for consciousness . Journal of Cognitive Science 19 , 115 - 124 .
[64]
Tsekov , R . ( 2012) Bohmian mechanics versus Madelung quantum hydrodynamics . In, V. Popov (ed.) Ananuire de l’Universite de Sofia, Faculte de Physique, Sofia University Press, Sofia .
[65]
Tuszynski , J. A ., Portet , S ., Dixon , J. M ., Luxford , C . and Cantiello , H. F . ( 2004) Ionic wave propagation along actin filaments . Biophysical Journal 86 , 1890 - 1903 . 10.1016/S0006-3495(04)74255-1 15041636 b156ebb83f23246b7a10c845f0938015 http%3A%2F%2Feuropepmc.org%2Farticles%2FPMC1304047 http://europepmc.org/articles/PMC1304047
[66]
Walshe , F. M. R . ( 1972). The neurophysiological approach to the problem of consciousness . In, M. Critchley, J.L. O’Learly, B. Jennet (eds.) Scientific Foundations of Neurology. London : Heinemann .
[67]
Woolf , N. J . and Butcher , L. L . ( 2011) Cholinergic systems mediate action from movement to higher consciousness . Behavioural Brain Research 221 , 488 - 498 . 10.1016/j.bbr.2009.12.046 20060422 5e17445863185cfad63080dbd6f23219 http%3A%2F%2Fwww.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov%2Fpubmed%2F20060422 http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/20060422
Share
Back to top